“Getting ready for the next war” Bertrand Russell’s political
by user
Comments
Transcript
“Getting ready for the next war” Bertrand Russell’s political
“Getting ready for the next war” Bertrand Russell’s political thought in the 1930s” In the 1930s Bertrand Russell published two major works of political analysis – Freedom versus Organization, a study of nineteenth century politics published in 1934 and Power, a historical survey of the varieties of power in economic and political life, published in 1938. Russell was proud of these works, feeling that they were more substantial than the pot-boilers economic necessity forced him to write in the early thirties. In his very valuable study of Russell’s political thought, Alan Ryan has summarized Russell’s works of the 1930s and judged these two the most valuable, but his treatment is brief enough to be developed in more detail. (1) The 1930s were busy and difficult years for Bertrand Russell. The Great Depression reduced his publishing royalties and lecturing fees; the death of his brother burdened him with unexpected debt; his second divorce was costly and acrimonious and his third marriage less tranquil than he hoped; his experimental school, Beacon Hill, lost money continuously. International events – Japan’s invasion of Manchuria, Italy’s invasion of Ethiopia, the Spanish Civil War, Hitler’s remilitarization of Germany – convinced Russell that the European Powers were headed toward a repeat of the Great War, made more terrible by new weapons. In spite of it all, Russell published at a hectic pace, producing several political works of merit, as well as pot-boilers and one true disaster. He worried that the next 1 Great War, whether the democracies won or lost, would destroy individual freedoms. (2) Russell still had to rely on publishing and lecturing to support his family and his experimental school Beacon Hill and his personal life was complicated and often tempestuous, so these works though his best work in the 1930s, are in part merely popular. But Russell brought to these works a career of political activism dating from 1914, a real interest in history and powerful analytical skills. Russell outlined his conception of history in 1904 and held to it the rest of his life. He argued that history could not be studied by the scientific method – in the first place history has no exactly repeating processes, and further while historical data are true or false (which is the scientific standard) data are also more significant or less significant (which is not a scientific criterion). Hence Russell judged scientific philosophies of history such as Marxism invalid. But the study of history remained important because it can widen our sympathies, provide heroes to emulate, teach humility and moderation in politics and place our lives in a wider and meaningful context. Russell was always interested in history, knew historians, read history and wrote a lot of it. (3) Russell’s best works of the 1930s were historical and necessarily so, since his chief concern was the inherently historical fear that liberalism was a fleeting episode whose end was near. The vast majority of mankind was now dominated by the massive organizations of state and industry and hence led lives of poverty, apathy, bleakness and fear, interrupted by episodes of scape-goating and fanaticism. What, Russell wondered, were the prospects for civilization after a cataclysm more terrible than the Great War? 2 Russell’s first serious work of the 1930s was The Scientific Outlook. In it Russell made the common-sense point that science had made the life of the average person both better by means of labor-saving devices and worse by means of new means of control for dictators to employ. If happiness is the ideal condition, Russell wondered if scientists should develop a non-addictive, mood – altering drug for general use. Aldous Huxley developed the idea into Brave New World, but Russell had challenged utilitarians to show why they should not endorse a system of pharmacological management of the populace by government. Russell maintained his utilitarian outlook by defining happiness as the stimulation of a creative, curious, independent, questing existence. But this redefinition of happiness may not be persuasive, and the challenge to utilitarianism would continue to complicate Russell’s political theory. (4) Russell began Freedom versus Organization with four chapters on the Congress of Vienna and the Congress System. The conclusions were conventional; the portraits of Metternich and Alexander I scathing. The next section, heavily indebted to the work of J.L. and Barbara Hammond, described the deplorable living conditions of agricultural workers and factory hands in early industrial England. Then he turned to picturing the most influential political schools of the day – the Philosophical Radicals and the Socialists. (5) Russell defended the Utilitarians as opponents of powerful institutions that needed opposing. He devoted a surprising amount of time to Richard Cobden, using Cobden as exemplar of Free Trade. Russell judged that Cobden was right to oppose the Crimean War and the extreme nationalism it provoked; Russell preferred the internationalism of free trade to the irrationalist nationalism of Crimean War advocates. Russell’s presentism showed clearly when he linked Crimean era nationalism to contemporary Nazi nationalism. 3 But Cobden, though admirable in his ideals, was wrong in his prediction. Free trade and male suffrage did not lead to pacifism; instead the working and middle classes became jingoists. Moreover Cobden erred when he imagined the benefits of economic competition to be the inescapable consequences of simple competition. Cobden did not recognize that competition had to be constrained by appropriate rules in order to produce general benefits. Cobden – and advocates of Manchester economics in general – ignored two other problems. First, competition can lead to a single winner, a monopoly. Second, the putatively beneficial competition of individuals can evolve into the possibly harmful competition of groups such as unions and nations. Although Cobden did not foresee and would not have approved the transformation, over time the Manchester ideal of beneficial individual competition was transformed into the propaganda of the Robber Barons by continuing to trumpet the virtues of competition and ignoring the decline of individual enterprises. Even worse in its manipulation of the Manchester ideal was Social Darwinism, which endorsed all forms of competition, including war, and credited victory to the genetic superiority of the winning individual or nation. Again, Russell’s presentism shows, for he linked the Social Darwinists of the late nineteenth century to contemporary Fascism. (6) Russell repeated in Freedom versus Organization the criticisms of Marxism he had made in earlier works. Russell rejected Marx’s vision of social conflict producing progress; Russell referred to “the next world war” and the slaughter it will bring as poison gas and bacteria are used. Russell denied the Hegel-inspired notion that conflict necessarily leads to a higher resolution, observing that conflict can and has led to decline and barbarism. Russell wagered that after the next 4 world war there would be no progressive transition to Communism but instead irrationalism and barbarism. (7) If the next Great War was a true class war of proletarians defeating capitalists, it would not be a simple matter of toppling a handful of capitalists, but a war of vast proportions since the ownership of capital was now wide-spread and capitalists had formidable allies among professionals, service sector employees, technicians, bureaucrats and skilled workers. The class hatred necessary to motivate proletarian victory could not be the basis on which to rebuild society. Proletarian peace-making, like the failed Versailles conference, would be wrecked by the intensity of desires for revenge. (8) The final chapters of Freedom versus Organization are an indictment of nationalism. Nationalist zeal, weapons of awesome destructiveness and irresponsible diplomacy conducted by handfuls of ministers produced the Great War and will produce other similar wars. The scale and power of modern organizations will lead to destruction of a wholly new order unless a sufficiently powerful form of world government can be instituted. (9) In the years after publishing Freedom versus Organization Russell continued to worry about the possibilities of a war even more terrible than World War One. In 1935 he wrote an essay identifying the declining social groups driven by anxiety and wounded pride that populated the Nazi movement. A movement so based on the desire for revenge would inevitably start a war. Russell followed this rather insightful essay by publishing the next year the greatest disaster of his career, Which Way to Peace? In that work he argued that it was better, since in total fewer lives would be lost, to accept Nazi conquest than to resist. As soon as Which Way to Peace? was published, Russell knew it was dead wrong and several years later publicly disavowed the work. (10) 5 Russell had believed for some time that the common man’s enthusiasm for World War One was a reaction against the regimentation and dullness of modern industrial life. Boredom bred bellicosity. And if so, the end of capitalist regimentation of daily life would make nations more peaceful. But Russell lost faith in this idea. Running an experimental school may have convinced him that aggression and cruelty are innate and therefore much harder to manage than he had previously supposed. However he came to this realization, it further weakened his hope for a peaceful future. (11) Power is based on a series of lectures Russell delivered at the London School of Economics in 1937. But while the site of the lectures was the LSE they had little influence on or connection to the intellectual life of the LSE. At the time of the lectures he wrote that his aim was to demonstrate that neither laissez-faire nor Marxism adequately accounted for economic power. (12) The leading lights of the LSE at the time, Lionel Robbins and Friedrich Hayek, were interested in debunking Keynes and not interested in Russell’s broad-bush historical economics. (13) Nor for that matter was Russell much interested in academic economics, whether the LSE or Cambridge type. Russell did not develop the ideas in Power but decided to return to research in philosophy and arranged to lecture at Oxford. (14) But if Power stands in isolation unrelated to contemporary works as well as Russell’s later works, it contains interesting elements. Russell ignored recent works by economists seeking to understand economic power. Classical economists had analyzed perfect competition and monopoly, but recently Joan Robinson at Cambridge and Edward Chamberlin at Harvard developed the concept of imperfect competition to explain the behavior of 6 producers with some power to set prices. (15) Of course Keynes had rejected the laissez-faire picture of markets smoothly responding to new conditions and pointed out the power of the irrational expectations of investors in determining the level of capital spending. (16) Russell proceeds without any reference to these works. Power employs a wealth of detail from ancient and medieval European history but does not employ the concept of authority. Hence it seems distant from contemporary sociological works on power and authority, but in fact Russell’s main conclusions on power are consistent with contemporary analyses. Contemporary sociology largely agrees with Russell’s propositions that (1) power is a fundamental phenomenon for the social sciences, (2) the desire for power is as strong a motive as the desire for wealth, (3) power takes many forms, and power of one type can be used to acquire power of another types and (4) the individual thirst for power is an important cause of social change. (17) But this consistency was not achieved deliberately; Russell wrote Power without reading the sociological literature. While Russell analyzed forms of power and means to restrain power, he had three contemporary problems in mind. The first was the extraordinary power over individuals that modern organizations, and especially the government, possessed. The second was the intensity and therefore the power of modern nationalism. The third was the fanaticism of the Nazi and Soviet regimes. The combination of these three conditions made war inevitable. Early in the work Russell imagines the result of a modern war characterized by mass bombing of cities. Russell concludes that whether London and Paris or Rome and Berlin won would make no difference; the winners would be brutalized by the means they used. (18) A later passage again hypothesizes a war of England 7 against Germany. (19) He identified four nations that ruled by fanaticism and demanded ideological conformity; they were Germany, Italy, Russia and Japan. (20) Russell rejects the idea that the Nazis, Fascists and Soviet Communists are normal political parties that somehow became extreme. These ruling parties began as secret revolutionary societies and hence were intense, conspiratorial, and deceitful from the beginning and by nature. (21) When Russell mentions nations with compromised sovereignty, his instances are Austria and Czechoslovakia, states whose sovereignty had been destroyed by Hitler. (22) Russell suggests that in the next Great War the democratic United States would likely be the big winner and the peace settlement would establish democracies in Eastern Europe, but the opposite outcome was also possible. In any case, the next war was not distant; it is a war “for which we are all preparing, at the cost – in Great Britain – of more than a quarter of our income.” (23) Amid the many topics in Power, there is a pattern discernible, a generalization built on Russell’s understanding of World War One. The desire for power (to lead others and make decisions for the group) is innate in human nature, but variable, stronger in some persons than in others, and capable of taking abnormal, exaggerated forms. The power to lead is necessary for groups to achieve those worthy goals that pure cooperation cannot achieve, but group achievement can be prevented or distorted by the selfishness, fanaticism or sadism of leaders. The unity of a group can be voluntary and enduring, temporary and tactical, coerced by violent regulation or instilled by education. Group cohesion thus depends on a mixture of self-interest, coercion and manipulation or education. In modern times the potential power of leaders increased tremendously as national feeling become more exploitable and the means to coerce and to educate become more effective. There were no inherent countervailing processes limiting the 8 accumulation of power. In the nineteenth century various figures believed that competition limited the accumulation of power – free competition in the market limited the economic power of buyers and sellers, free competition in the market place of ideas limited the power of dogma and illusion, a kind of biological competition limited the size and life of social units. But Russell demonstrated that the effectiveness of competition was illusory. And there was a terrible process made possible by modern conditions of organization and control. New regimes, whether resting on naked power or ideological fanaticism, could use propaganda and war-mongering to develop loyalty. These totalitarian regimes might be destroyed in the wars they fomented, but the successor states designed in the devastated aftermath of defeat were unlikely grounds for developing stable, peaceful democracies, so the rise of tyrannical regimes was likely to repeat. From this pattern there seemed no escape. Russell was convinced that there would be a second Great War, even more destructive than the first, and that its settlement would do as little to bring peace and civility as had the Versailles Treaty. We could judge this theory a hasty generalization built on the single example of World War One. Alternatively we could say that tendencies in human nature combined with the mixed legacy of scientific advances created in World War One a major event that made the future heavily path – dependent. It would be wrong to lavish praise on Russell for recognizing the obvious – the 1930s was the decade of dictators as all could see. But in fact many did not wish to see. Appeasers in England believed concessions to Hitler could moderate his behavior. Isolationists in the United States believed that the next war could be confined to Europe. The far right in France proclaimed “Better Hitler than Blum.” 9 Like all the other political commentators of the time Russell was unable to envision a workable means to avoid war. Critics have made two charges. First, they fault him for alternating among proposed means to peace – in his case, guild socialism, pacifism, world government – too rapidly. Second, they fault him for failing to spell out any of his proposals in sufficient detail to win converts. Admitting the merit of these points, there are sufficient strong points in his two major political works of the 1930s to support a more balanced final estimate. Russell, we should remember, warned that individual liberty must be preserved in a society of giant organizations and recommended political devolution as one means to that end. He noticed how ideological movements evolve into military organizations that embrace xenophobia to remain in power. He recognized the value of the competitive spirit in motivating individuals but warned against supposed wonder-working powers of competition. He warned how formidable the problems of post-war social reconstruction are and observed how fragile new democracies are. These warnings, which have not lost their relevance, constitute Russell’s contribution to political thought in the 1930s. Endnotes 1. Alan Ryan, Bertrand Russell: A Political Life (Hill and Wang; New York, 1988). 2. Caroline Moorehead, Bertrand Russell: A Life (Viking: New York, 1992). 10 3. Kirk Willis, “Bertrand Russell on History: the Theory and Practice of a Moral Science,” pp. 116-37 in Bernard P. Dauenhauer, ed., At the Nexus of Philosophy and History (Athens: University of Georgia press, 1987). Russell’s essay, “On History” is available in Robert E. Egner and Lester E. Dennon, eds., The Basic Writings of Bertrand Russell (Simon and Schuster: New York, 1961) pp. 521-27. 4. I rely on Alan Ryan, Bertrand Russell: A Political Life (Hill and Wang: New York, 1988) pp. 129-36. 5. For chronological order Malthus appears among the Philosophical Radicals. 6. Russell, Freedom versus Organization, (New York: W.W. Norton, 1962 [1st ed., 1934]) Ch. 14. 7. Op. cit., Ch. 18. 8. Op. cit., Ch. 20. 9. Op. cit., Ch. 32. 10. I rely on Ryan, Bertrand Russell, pp. 116, 144-50 for this summary. 11. Moorehead, Bertrand Russell, p. 403. 12. Bertrand Russell, Autobiography, Vol. II (Boston: Little, Brown, 1968) pp. 289-90. 11 13. Nicholas Wapshott, Keynes/Hayek (New York: W.W. Norton, 2011) 14. The Selected Letters of Bertrand Russell. Vol. II. Ed. By Nicholas Griffin (London: Routledge, 2001) pp. 351-52. Russell to Warden Norton. 15. A devastating portrait of Robinson appears in Sylvia Nasar, Grand Pursuit (New York, Simon & Schuster, 2011) Ch. XI. 16. The interpretation of Keynes remains controversial. I follow Keynes biographer Robert Skidelsky in stressing Keynes’ dissent form neo-classical economic theory. 17. For this generalization I draw on Brigid C. Harrison and Thomas R. Dye, Power and Society (Cengage: Mason, Ohio, 2008) p. 6. 18. Bertrand Russell, Power: A New Social Analysis (New York: W.W. Norton, 1938) p. 33. 19. Op. cit., p. 150. 20. Op. cit., p. 148. 21. Op. cit., p. 171. 22. Op. cit., p. 181. 12 23. Op. cit., p. 212. Bibliography Clark, Ronald W. The Life of Bertrand Russell. New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1976 Lauren, Paul Gordon, Gordon A. Craig and Alexander L. George. Force and Statecraft: Diplomatic Challenges of Our Time. 4th ed. New York: Oxford University Press. Moorehead, Caroline. Bertrand Russell: A Life. New York: Viking, 1992. Nasar, Sylvia. Grand Pursuit: The Story of Economic Genius. New York: Simon and Schuster, 2011. Nisbet, Robert A. The Sociological Tradition. 2nd ed. New Brunswick, N.J.: Transaction Publishers, 1993. Pojman, Louis P. Global Political Philosophy. Boston: McGraw Hill, 2003. Robbins, Lord. The Evolution of Modern Economic Theory. London: Macmillan, 1970. Rowse, A. L. Appeasement: A Study of Political Decline, 1933-1939. New York: W.W. Norton, 1963. Russell, Bertrand. Autobiography. Vol II – 1914-1944. Boston: Little, Brown, 1968. __________. The Basic Writings of Bertrand Russell, ed. by Robert E. Egner and Lester E. Denonn. New York: Simon and Schuster, 1961. __________. Freedom versus Organization, 1814 – 1914. London: Unwin, 1934. __________. German Social Democracy. New York: Simon and Schuster, 1965 [1st ed. 1896]. __________. In Praise of Idleness, and Other Essays. London: Unwin, 1935. 13 __________. Political Ideals. London: Unwin, 1963 [1st ed. 1917]. __________. Power: A New Social Analysis. New York: W. W. Norton, 1938. __________. The Practice and Theory of Bolshevism. London: Unwin, 1920. __________. Principles of Social Reconstruction. London: Unwin, 1916. __________. Roads to Freedom. London: Unwin, 1918. __________. The Selected Letters of Bertrand Russell. The Public Years, 1914 – 1970. ed. by Nicholas Griffin. London: Routledge, 2001. Ryan, Alan. The Making of Modern Liberalism. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2012. __________. Bertrand Russell: A Political Life. New York: Hill and Wang, 1988. Skidelsky, Robert. Keynes: The Return of the Master. New York: Public Affairs, 2010. Taylor, A. J. P. English History, 1914 – 1945. London: Oxford University Press, 1965. Wapshott, Nicholas. Keynes/Hayek: The Clash That Defined Modern Economics. New York: W. W. Norton, 2011. Willis, Kirk. “Bertrand Russell on History: The Theory and Practice of a Moral Science.” In At the Nexus of Philosophy and History, ed. by Bernard Davenhauer. Athens, Ga.: University of Georgia Press, 1987. Winch, Donald. Economics and Policy: A Historical Survey. London: Hodder and Stoughton, 1969. 14